©
2002 Psychiatric Times. All rights reserved.
Addiction Is a Choice
by Jeffrey A. Schaler,
Ph.D.
Psychiatric Times
October 2002
Vol. XIX
Issue 10
(Please see Counterpoint
article by by John H. Halpern, M.D.)
Is addiction a disease, or is it a choice? To think
clearly about this question, we need to make a sharp
distinction between an activity and its results. Many
activities that are not themselves diseases can cause
diseases. And a foolish, self-destructive activity is not
necessarily a disease.
With those two vital points in mind, we observe a person
ingesting some substance: alcohol, nicotine, cocaine or
heroin. We have to decide, not whether this pattern of
consumption causes disease nor whether it is foolish and
self-destructive, but rather whether it is something
altogether distinct and separate: Is this pattern of drug
consumption itself a disease?
Scientifically, the contention that addiction is a
disease is empirically unsupported. Addiction is a behavior
and thus clearly intended by the individual person. What is
obvious to common sense has been corroborated by pertinent
research for years (Table
1).
The person we call an addict always monitors their
rate of consumption in relation to relevant circumstances.
For example, even in the most desperate, chronic cases,
alcoholics never drink all the alcohol they can. They plan
ahead, carefully nursing themselves back from the last
drinking binge while deliberately preparing for the next
one. This is not to say that their conduct is wise, simply
that they are in control of what they are doing. Not only is
there no evidence that they cannot moderate their drinking,
there is clear evidence that they do so, rationally
responding to incentives devised by hospital researchers.
Again, the evidence supporting this assertion has been known
in the scientific community for years (Table
2).
My book Addiction Is a Choice was criticized in a
recent review in a British scholarly journal of addiction
studies because it states the obvious (Davidson, 2001).
According to the reviewer, everyone in the addiction field
now knows that addiction is a choice and not a disease, and
I am, therefore, "violently pushing against a door which was
opened decades ago." I'm delighted to hear that addiction
specialists in Britain are so enlightened and that there is
no need for me to argue my case over there.
In the United States, we have not made so much progress.
Why do some persist, in the face of all reason and all
evidence, in pushing the disease model as the best
explanation for addiction?
I conjecture that the answer lies in a fashionable
conception of the relation between mind and body. There are
several competing philosophical theories about that
relation. Let us accept, for the sake of argument, the most
extreme "materialist" theory: the psychophysical identity
theory. Accordingly, every mental event corresponds to a
physical event, because it is a physical event. The relation
between mind and the relevant parts of the body is,
therefore, like the relation between heat and molecular
motion: They are precisely the same thing, observed in two
different ways. As it happens, I find this view of the
relation between mind and body very congenial.
However, I think it is often accompanied by a serious
misunderstanding: the notion that when we find a parallel
between physiological processes and mental or personality
processes, the physiological process is what is really going
on and the mental process is just a passive result of the
physical process. What this overlooks is the reality of
downward causation, the phenomenon in which an
emergent property of a system can govern the position of
elements within the system (Campbell, 1974; Sperry, 1969).
Thus, the complex, symmetrical, six-pointed design of a snow
crystal largely governs the position of each molecule of ice
in that crystal.
Hence, there is no theoretical obstacle to acknowledging
the fact that thoughts, desires, values and other mental
phenomena can dominate bodily functions. Suppose that a
man's mother dies, and he undergoes the agonizing trauma we
call unbearable grief. There is no doubt that if we
examine this man's bodily processes we will find many
physical changes, among them changes in his blood and
stomach chemistry. It would be clearly wrong to say that
these bodily changes cause him to be grief-stricken. It
would be less misleading to say that his being
grief-stricken causes the bodily changes, but this is also
not entirely accurate. His knowledge of his mother's death
(interacting with his prior beliefs and values) causes his
grief, and his grief has blood-sugar and gastric
concomitants, among many others.
There is no dispute that various substances cause
physiological changes in the bodies of people who ingest
them. There is also no dispute, in principle, that these
physiological changes may themselves change with repeated
doses, nor that these changes may be correlated with
subjective mental states like reward or enjoyment.
I say "in principle" because I suspect that people
sometimes tend to run away with these supposed correlations.
For example, changes in dopamine levels have often been
hypothesized as an integral part of the reward/reinforcement
process. Yet research shows that dopamine in the nucleus
accumbens does not mediate primary or unconditioned food
reward in animals (Aberman and Salamone, 1999; Nowend et
al., 2001; Salamone et al., 2001; Salamone et al., 1997).
According to Salamone, the theory that drugs of abuse turn
on a natural reward system is simplistic and inaccurate:
"Dopamine in the nucleus accumbens plays a role in the
self-administration of some drugs (i.e., stimulants), but
certainly not all" (personal communication, Nov. 26, 2001).
Garris et al. (1999) reached similar conclusions:
"Dopamine may therefore be a neural substrate for novelty or
reward expectation rather than reward itself." They
concluded:
[T]here is no correlation between continual bar
pressing during [intracranial self-stimulation] and
increased dopaminergic neurotransmission in the nucleus
accumbens…our results are consistent with evidence that
the dopaminergic component is not associated with the
hedonistic or 'pleasure' aspects of reward…Likewise, the
rewarding effects of cocaine do not require dopamine; mice
lacking the gene for the dopamine transporter, a major
target of cocaine, will self-administer cocaine. However,
increased dopamine neurotransmission in the nucleus
accumbens shell is seen when rats are transiently exposed
to a new environment. The increase in extracellular
dopamine quickly returns to normal levels and remains
there during continued exploration of the new
environment…dopamine release in the nucleus accumbens is
related to novelty, predictability or some other aspects
of the reward process, rather than to hedonism itself.
Perhaps, then, some people have been too ready to jump to
conclusions about specific mechanisms. Be that as it may,
chemical rewards have no power to compel--although this
notion of compulsion may be a cherished part of clinicians'
folklore. I am rewarded every time I eat chocolate cake, but
I often eschew this reward because I feel I ought to watch
my weight.
Experience with addiction treatment must surely make us
even more dubious about the theory that addiction is a
disease. The most popular way of helping people manage their
addictive behavior is Alcoholics Anonymous (AA) and its
various 12-step offshoots. Many observers have recognized
the essentially religious nature of AA. The U.S. courts are
increasingly regarding AA as a religious activity. In
United States v Seeger (1965), the U.S. Supreme Court
stated that the test to be applied as to whether a belief is
religious is to enquire whether that belief "occupies a
place in the life of its possessor parallel to that filled
by the orthodox belief in God" in religions more widely
accepted in the United States. This requirement is met by
members of AA and other secular programs that help people
with addictive behaviors and encourage their members to turn
their will and lives over to the care of a supreme being.
What kind of disease is this for which the best available
treatment is religion (Antze, 1987)? Clinical applications
are based on explanations for why the behavior occurs. An
activity based on a religious belief masquerading as a
clinical form of treatment tells us something about what the
activity really is--an ethical, not medical, problem in
living.
What passes as clinical treatment for addiction is
psychotherapy, which essentially consists of various forms
of conversation or rhetoric (Szasz, 1988). One person, the
therapist, tries to influence another person, the patient,
to change their values and behavior. While the conversation
called therapy can be helpful, most of the conversation that
occurs in therapy based on the disease model is potentially
harmful. This is because the therapist misleads the patient
into believing something that is simply untrue--that
addiction is a disease, and, therefore, addicts cannot
control their behavior. Preaching this falsehood to patients
may encourage them to abandon any attempt to take
responsibility for their actions.
The treatment of drug effects, at the patient's request,
is well within the domain of medicine, what passes as
evidence for the theory that addiction is a disease is
merely clinical folklore.
Dr. Schaler teaches at American University's School of
Public Affairs in Washington, D.C., and at Johns Hopkins
University in Baltimore. Addiction is a Choice (Open Court
Publishers, 2000) is among his published works on
addiction.
References
Aberman JE, Salamone JD (1999), Nucleus accumbens
dopamine depletions make rats more sensitive to high ratio
requirements but do not impair primary food reinforcement.
Neuroscience 92(2):545-552.
Antze P (1987), Symbolic action in Alcoholics Anonymous.
In: Constructive Drinking: Perspectives on Drink From
Anthropology, Douglas M, ed. New York: Cambridge University
Press, pp149-181.
Campbell DT (1974), 'Downward causation' in
hierarchically organized biological systems. In: Studies in
the Philosophy of Biology: Reduction and Related Problems,
Ayala FJ, Dobzhansky T, eds. London: Macmillan.
Davidson R (2001), Conspiracy, cults and choices.
Addiction Research & Theory 9(1):92-92 [book
review].
Garris PA, Kilpatrick M, Bunin MA et al. (1999),
Dissociation of dopamine release in the nucleus accumbens
from intracranial self-stimulation. Nature
398(6722):67-69.
Nowend KL, Arizzi M, Carlson BB, Salamone JD (2001), D1
or D2 antagonism in nucleus accumbens core or dorsomedial
shell suppresses lever pressing for food but leads to
compensatory increases in chow consumption. Pharmacol
Biochem Behav 69(3-4):373-382.
Salamone JD, Cousins MS, Snyder BJ (1997), Behavioral
functions of nucleus accumbens dopamine: empirical and
conceptual problems with the anhedonia hypothesis. Neurosci
Biobehav Rev 21(3):341-359.
Salamone JD, Wisniecki A, Carlson BB, Correa M (2001),
Nucleus accumbens dopamine depletions make animals highly
sensitive to high fixed ratio requirements but do not impair
primary food reinforcement. Neuroscience 105(4):863-870.
Sperry W (1969), A modified concept of consciousness.
Psychol Rev 76(6):532-536.
Szasz TS (1988), The Myth of Psychotherapy: Mental
Healing as Religion, Rhetoric, and Repression. Syracuse,
N.Y.: Syracuse University Press.
United States v Seeger, 980 US 163 (1965).